Tuesday 24 November 2015

Marie Antoinette - French Revolution

As Queen of France, Marie Antoinette had no official role and no legitimate political power — her main job was to produce a male heir to continue her husband's royal line.  Like the marriage, the coronation of Louis XVI was greeted warmly by the French people, who had great hopes that after the fifty-year reign of  Louis XV, the young King would bring new ideas, much-needed reforms, and a fresh approach to governing France in a rapidly-changing world.


This goodwill quickly eroded as the King's economic policies failed, while his Queen failed to produce an heir.  He seemed to lose interest in government, as she became aggressively social, attending the Opera and dances in the capital, gambling and  partying late into the night at Versailles.  In public and at court she was seen only in the latest and most expensive fashions. Rumors about her alleged secret lovers and out-of-control spending increased.

Illegal presses began printing pamphlets showing the queen as an ignorant, adulterous spendthrift.  Some speculated in print that the King's brother, the comte d'Artois, was taking the King's place in his wife's bed.  Louis XVI was the first French king in two hundred years not to have a royal mistress;  Marie Antoinette was the first queen to believe that she could be both wife and mistress to her husband. However, by cultivating fashion, taste, and the arts while failing to produce a legitimate heir, Marie Antoinette looked to all the world like a mistress, not a wife, and one whose sexuality was directed away from the King.  All the ire that had been directed at Madame de Pompadour and Madame du Barry, Louis XV's most famous mistresses, was now redirected at the only target available: the Queen who acted like a mistress, but who was not satisfied, it seemed, with the King.

Marie Antoinette's first child, Marie Therese Charlotte, was finally born in December 1778, followed by Louis Joseph in 1781, Louis Charles in 1785 and Sophie Béatrix in 1786. As she grew older, the Queen became less extravagant, devoting herself to her children, two of whom died in childhood.  In fact, her first son, the dauphin, died on June 4, 1789.  This meant that the Queen was in mourning for her son when the Tennis Court Oath was signed on June 20, the Bastille fell on July 14, and still when the Great Fear spread throughout the countryside in August.

In October 1789, the royal family was forced to leave Versailles for the Tuileries palace in the heart of Paris, where they lived in prison-like isolation. Marie Antoinette secretly requested help from other European rulers, including her royal siblings in Austria and Naples. On the night of June 20, 1791, the royal family attempted to flee.  Their escape plan was said to have been engineered by Axel von Fersen, the Swedish count who was rumored to be one of the Queen's lovers.  It is incontestable that Marie Antoinette's brother awaited the royal family just across the border and that he was accompanied by troops ready to invade.   They were caught in the small town of Varennes, half-way to the border, and brought back to Paris, prisoners now of the Revolutionary government.

On the night of August 10, 1792, militants attacked the royal palace where Marie Antoinette and her family were being held and forced the Legislative Assembly to "suspend" the King.  Little more than a month later, on September 20, the new National Convention  was convened, and two days later it voted to declare France a republic, thus abolishing the monarchy.  From that moment on, Louis XVI and Marie Antoinette were no longer King and Queen, but, like many others, imprisoned citizens suspected of treason.

Marie Antoinette became a widow when her husband was guillotined to death after being tried and convicted of treason in January 1793.  Her two remaining children were subsequently taken from her. After a brief trial, Marie Antoinette herself was convicted of treason and also of sexual abuse of her son in October 1793.  On October 16,  she too was executed by guillotine. She was 37 years old.

Sunday 8 November 2015

Jean Baudrillard's Theory of Hyperreality


“Is this the real life, is this just fantasy, caught in a land slide no escape from reality”, sings Queen in Bohemian Rhapsody, this is a good way to introduce Jean Baudrillard, an advocate against hyperreality, who one could call a Bohemian.

 Arguably, Baudrillard’s most famous work in the late 1980’s and into the 1990’s was “America ”, “Simulacra and Simulations ” and “The Gulf War Did Not Take Place ”, All of these works; as do the majority of his other work that came out of the 90’s, argue that humanity is allowing the world to slip away from true reality and into the realm of what he calls the "hyperreal".


 Baudrillard’s notion of hyperreality is, that we have allowed ourselves to be blinded from true reality, replacing it instead with simulations of the real that are perceived by humans as being more real than true reality I.E television, ads, the internet, newspapers, videogames, etc. Dilbert would put it another way, “We live in a cold mechanistic technocracy, we have to make that work ”. In this Guide entry, you will be introduced to Baudrillard’s origins as a Marxist philosopher, his move away from Marxism, and by using examples from “The Ecstasy of Communication”, “Simulacra and Simulation’ and “The Gulf War Did Not Take Place” lay out some of the basic concepts and terminology one needs in order to approach his later works on the subjects of Simulacra and simulation.


Baudrillard Marx the Spot

Karl Marx heavily influenced Baudrillard’s early work. To understand the influence Marxism had on Baudrillard one must first understand the theory of Marxism. “Marxism is the primary methodology of most economic analysis of…mass communications in general. Such studies involve not only questions of finance, production, and marketing, but also state policies. ” A Marxist looks at the vast majority of modern concerns such as, politics, economics, social behaviors, and media influence. Marxists also analyze the holistic connection between individual concerns, for example, economics and social behaviors, and then show how they can affect one another. One can see Marxist theories present in Baudrillards work wherein he talks specifically about economics, superficiality, and materialism. Though they will not be discussed here, it is worth noting that Baudrillard’s four logics of objects also relate back to Marxism (Appendix A), reading them, while not absolutely necessary, will allow you a more complex understanding of his work.

The Postmodernist always Looks Twice

In the 1980’s Baudrillard branched away from his Marxist influence claiming that Marxism, in fact, held the same basic worldview as capitalism. In society’s eyes, his new views classify him as postmodern, even though he proclaims himself not to be. Postmodernism means his ideas are rather unorthodox in comparison to the modernist outlook, that is, his ideas and opinions exist outside the realm of the conformist majority, which is what we call the modernist way of thinking. Thus, even though in Baudrillard’s eyes his views are not postmodern, due, unfortunately, to our societies want to taxonomies in modernist culture, others have stuck him with a postmodern label.

Baudrillard now argued against Marxism, claiming that the “Virus of bourgeois thought” influenced Marx. Now, Baudrillard is saying that the Marxist theory agrees with the capitalistic American system wherein society is centered on a concern for material interest and dominated by commercial and industrial means. It is in his essay “America” that he first claims American society to be completely hyperreal. Herein he states that the American culture is ruled by simulacra and simulation that the inhabitants falsely perceive as true reality. According to him, the entirety of the social world will eventually slip into this hyperreality, with little hope for saving it. He calls this future state of the world “The death of the real ”. In this regard, Baudrillard holds America as the model for our future for in the essay he calls America “The Finished form of the future catastrophe ”; even going as far as saying that America’s true form is cinematic. He also states that an individual who comes to America does not need to sit in an auditorium to witness cinema, in America, one need only look everywhere else. “The whole country is cinematic”, he says, further, only America has this power of cinematographisation of everyday life. Baudrillard is being a tad redundant here; he is simply restating that artifice is built into the American cultural ideology. One can see Baudrillards Marxist roots in the above statements. A Marxist theorist could make a holistic connection between the medium of hyperreality, in this case American culture, and the simulacra of film. On a side not A Marxist theorist could further say that film (or any other form of simulacra for that matter) and hyperreality are, in America’s case, co-dependently parasitic.


Back to the Past to look at the Present

Our society has come to a state where our personalities are based upon the brand logos we choose to wear. It’s so easy to stereotype my generation (Generation Y) because we do it ourselves. My generation has grown up on the stereotypes of TV in which the media thinks that they are reflecting our sense of society as reality. The realization is that these stereotypes have transduced our culture into that of the media’s version of reality. The fact is that every decision that we make about culture, dress and language can be linked to the media. - (Griffin, Monsters, Mad Prophets and Tribes, Oh My!)

The groundwork for Baudrillard’s theory of hyperreality was laid out in his 1983 book “The Ecstasy of Communication” wherein he scribes how multi-media saturated societies relinquish themselves to what he calls an “ecstasy of communication”. That is to say we hand ourselves over to the seductive power of the mass media (television, ads, films, magazines, and newspapers). “He says that the luminous eyes of television and computer screens penetrate into our private spaces in an ecstatic and obscene way, in this way our secrets disappear, and the images we consume become more and more pornographic”.

His message could be interpreted to mean that our over saturation of media images (what Baudrillard calls simulacra) allows the willing members of society to enter a catatonic state of multi-medium simulations (our Ecstasy of communication) wherein they become vulnerable to attacks on all of their senses; his use of the word "pornographic" can be mutiply interpetted, that is not to be used solely in regard to the images we are viewing in this state as becomeing progressively more risqué. One interpretation of the term "pornographic", as it is used in the cotext of his arugment, could mean that, in the state of viewer/consumer ecstasy that we enter into, our mode of spectatorship also becomes progressively more perverse. In such a case the term "secret", in the way he uses it, would be in relation to the spectators gaze at the images, as the images extract the spectators desires. Our "secrets" disappear into the images and are manifested in our minds as we consume them. So, if we use that interpretation, the manifestation or our disires combined with our inability to turn away from the simulations or to simply ignore them would also be part of the "pornography" in which he speaks; it is our indulgence in excess that causes the images to become more "pornographic". The simulations allow us an outlet for our own desires so we demand more of them. Over time, our minds become desensitized to the simulations so we demand ones that are more realistic. As this vicious cycle of desensitization continues, the simulations become more "pornographic" in televised form as a direct result of our demand for them to do so. In short, everyone is an active participant in the transition to hyperreality that will eventually cause “the death of the real”.

If you find this hard to consume, allow me to explain with an analogy. Let’s say you stop at a stop light near a railroad crossing. You look out the window; to your left you notice a train had a head on collision with another car. An ambulance with illuminating red lights and body bags is by the car, you watch as the paramedics attempt to salvage the bodies from the wreckage. Meanwhile you have completely forgotten that the stop light has turned green and the people behind you are honking their horns. Now I ask you, in this analogy, what, or who is perverse, the accident for happening or you for your inability to turn away?


Anyone for Sim Gulf?

The very definition of the real becomes: that of which it is possible to give an equivalent reproduction...At the limit of this process of reproducibility, the real is not only what can be reproduced, but that which is always already reproduced. The hyperreal…transcends representation…only because it is entirely in simulation… [A]rtifice is at the very heart of reality.

One of the best examples of Jean Baudrillard’s iconoclast theory of simulacra and simulation is “The Gulf War Did Not Take Place” wherein he attacks the versatility of the hyperreality of television news broadcasting. In the early 1990’s shortly before the beginning of the Gulf War Baudrillard proclaimed that the war would not actually accrue, after the event, he would not refute this statement proclaiming that he was right. We will come to reilize that from a hyperrealistic standpoint he was correct. It is important to remember in Baudrillards mind what we would call the actualities presented on television newscast are, to him, nothing more than simulations of the real events, they are copies and therefore they are not real. So, he did not say the gulf war did not happen, he simply said that what was televised for mass consumption by the non-enlisted citizens of America, being that they are images, are copies of the real events and therefore unreal. The true reality of the events that transpired in the Gulf War lie solely with those whom experienced the war first hand, all other secondary images, and thoughts are simulation. In short, the images we see on television, even the actualities portrayed on the news, are not real. Despite our cognitive notion to believe otherwise, the only events that are real are those that an individual experiences first hand. Therefore, in this case the experience of the men and women who were directly involved with the affair are the only ones to experience the reality. To everyone else it is simulation. This brought up an even more poignant notion for Baudrillard who now questioned the ability for there to be a real war in a modern society where our fighting is heavily aided by mechanized contraptions that do the fighting and scouting for us. Wikipedia explains his point nicely:

The real conflict, according to Baudrillard, was not a war with Iraq over the invasion of Kuwait but a great question concerning thee concept of war. The first Gulf War served as a crisis point determining whether or not war was still possible in the post-industrial age.

What’s for Desert?

One should be familiar with “the desert of the real” before approaching Baudrillard's latter work. Baudrillard uses this term for the fist time in his essay “the Precision of Simulacra”, in which he recounts a Borges tail about a an emperor who made a map so huge that it spanned the entirety of his empire. The map was so richly detailed that it overlaid the true empire. Eventually, the citizens came to accept the simulacrum as the true empire. Over time, the map started to show signs of aging and eventually completely disintegrated. The true empire that used to lie underneath the map was no more, instead in its place was the emptiness of the desert. The true reality had been destroyed by the simulation, replaced with “the desert of the real”

“The desert of the real” is an essential term to know; it actually sums up Baudrillards theory of hyperreality quite nicely. The term is often used when discussing topics that coincide with theories of simulacra, simulation and hyperreality.

Welcome to the Desert

Jean Baudrillard’s work offers a fascinating perspective on society. While his theories draw an array of criticisms (whose don’t) his views on the degradation of modern culture bring forth important issues about post-industrial culture. However, his work is dense and somewhat redundant. Using his basic notion of simulacra and simulation he argues in various essays that everything from Disneyland to money offer some form of semiotic connection to hyperreality. By reading this entry, you have come away with the bare basics of his latter work on hyperreality, and hopefully, those of you who wish to start the voyage back into true reality, have come away better prepared. Just remember to bring a pair of sunglasses and some sunscreen, you’re going to need them. Welcome to the desert of the real.


Appendix A: The Four Logics of Objects

1. The functional value of an object is its instrumental purpose. (A pen writes. A diamond ring adorns an otherwise empty hand.) This is what Marx referred to as the 'use-value' of the commodity.

2. The exchange value of an object is its economic value. (A pen is worth three pencils. A diamond ring is worth three months' salary.)


3. The symbolic exchange value of an object is its arbitrarily assigned and agreed value in relation to another subject. (A pen represents a graduation present or a speaker's gift. A diamond ring symbolizes a public declaration of love between two individuals.)

4. The sign exchange value of an object represents its value in a system of objects. (A pen is part of a desk set, or a particular pen confers social status. A diamond ring has sign exchange value in relation to other diamond rings, conferring social status to the person with the biggest or prettiest ring.)
------------------------------




a. Introduction
See pp. 355-358 and 410-415 of The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory.
The following notes discuss the writings of Jean Baudrillard as an example of a self-conscious postmodern approach. Baudrillard has become the examplar of postmodernism, beginning his analysis with Marxism and modernity, and developing what he considered a more radical approach – a society of simulations, implosions and hyperreality, where it is increasingly difficult to distinguish image from reality and where signs and simulations become or are society. Following this approach from the 1970s, Baudrillard develops the view that we are at the end of history and history may be reversing itself, so we live in a "post-orgy state of things" (Baudrillard in Best and Kellner, 1991, p. 137). This leads him to a cynical conclusion that all we can do is "reach a point where one can live with what is left. It is more a survival among the ruins than anything else" (Baudrillard in Best and Kellner, 1997, p. 117), although survival in the ruins usually means that people begin to rebuild. In spite of his conclusions, many of the ideas of Baudrillard are insightful and provide a useful way of considering the contemporary era.
Jean Baudrillard (1929 – present) was born in Rheims, France in a civil servant family. He taught German and then became a sociology professor at the University of Nanterre from the 1960s through 1987. His most famous works are The Mirror of Production (1975), Simulacres et Simulation (1981, translated into English in 1994), and the controversial The Gulf War did not take place (1995). In France, Baudrillard is a public intellectual, who makes pronouncements on current phenomena and is regarded by some as a postmodern guru – like McLuhan in the 1960s or John Raulston Saul in Canada today. Two of the articules in the handouts were written for the Paris Libération, a daily newspaper widely read throughout France by intellectuals, professionals, and people on the political left.
Many of the notes that follow come from the two books by Best and Kellner (BK).
b. Early WritingsIn his early work, Baudrillard began by examining modernity, the consumer society, and Marxism in a fairly conventional manner. Like the critical theorists, he examined the development of "the new system of mass consumption bound up with the explosive proliferation of consumer goods and services" which creates a "‘new technical order’, ‘new environment’, ‘new field of everyday life’, ‘new morality’, and new form of ‘hypercivilization’" (BK, 1991, p. 112-3). The mass commodification and expansion of exchange values has vastly expanded in contemporary capitalism, so that objects, signs, and exchange value dominate society and the people in society. Like other analysts of modernity, Baudrillard takes a look back to the premodern and notes that while exchange occurred in these societies, it was symbolic exchange – gifts and reciprocity associated with various rituals, spirituality, or other forms of social obligation. These systems tended to reinforce tradition, rather than separating people from it as is the case with commodity exchange.
With capitalism, exchange value comes to dominate the exchange of goods, so that markets, quantitative calculation of exchange values, and money become the dominant form. Political economy develops as a mode of analysing this, and production and the needs of production come to dominate society. For Baudrillard, even Marxian political economy may be part of the system of rationalization and reproduction of the capitalist order. That is, Marxian political economy argues that capitalism is exploitative and inefficient in production, and in arguing for socialism and communism posits a better form of organization of production and exchange. That is, Marxism does not challenge the logic of the primacy of production in directing society and creating progress, and this is whre Baudrillard begins to develop a differerent approach.
Baudrillard begins his argument by noting that in addition to use and exchange value, there is also "sign value, whereby commodities are valued by the way that they confer prestige and signify social status and power" (BK, 1991, p. 114). While Marx argues that use values are given, and exchange value implies the existence of use value, Baudrillard notes that use values themselves are problematic, in that they are constructed through exchange value and "a rationalized system of needs and objects that integrate individuals into the capitalist social order" (BK, 1991, p. 114). In making this argument, he does not move beyond critical theorists, who made much the same type of argument.
Where Baudrillard begins to develop his ideas in a different direction is to emphasize symbols and symbolic exchange. In his writings in the early and mid 1970s, he argued for a return to symbolic exchange as a means of breaking the logic and demands of production, commodity exchange, and political economy. Symbolic exchange could be revolutionary in that it "provides a mode of activity that is more radically subversive of the values and logic of capitalism than the sort of practices advocated by Marxists which he claims are but a reflex of the ‘mirror of production’" (BK, 1991, p. 116). At this time, Baudrillard was impressed with marginal groups such as blacks, women, and gays, what sociologists have termed the new social movements, which "subvert the code of racial or sexual difference, and thus are more radical and subversive than socialists who operate within the code of political economy" (BK, 1991, p. 116). These arguments were developed in the aftermath of the 1968 events in France, where radical change initially seemed possible, but was thwarted by traditional forces, including some of the established socialist and communist parties and groupings. Out of this grew various ultraleft and new types of groups which argued for a radical break with the dominant economic and political forms.
c. Simulations, Implosion, and HyperrealitySmart (pp. 411-12) notes how Baudrillard regards Marxist thought as part of the Enlightenment and westerm culture, part of a universalist approach that misconceives what has happened in western and other societies. In the later 1970s and during the 1980s, Baudrillard’s analysis broke with the Marxist approach and expanded on the view that symbols, signs, and simulations had become so all-encompassing, that it is not longer possible to distinguish the real and the symbol. Baudrillard thus argues that we have entered a new era that is beyond the modern, and this constitutes a break with an earlier era – much like the break between the premodern and the modern.
In the modern era, the problems of industry, production, use of labour, exploitation, and accumulation dominated the organization of the economy and society. In the current period there is "a new era of simulation in which computerization, information processing, media, cybernetic control systems, and the organization of society according to simulation codes and models replace production as the organizing principle of society" (BK, 1991, p. 118). This is a passage "‘from a metallurgic into a semiurgic society’ … in which signs take on a life of their own and constitute a new social order structured by models, codes, and signs" (BK, 1991, p. 118).
Semiotics refers to the theory of signs – types, meaning, relationships among signs. A sign is any information carrying entity from language to road signs.
What Baudrillard is arguing is that the signs, simulations, and codes that characterize the current era have developed to a point that it is these that structure society and make it difficult to distinguish these signs and symbols from social reality – or the social reality becomes the signs and simulations and these structure the social world. In developing this analysis, Baudrillard develops several new concepts.
Simulation or Simulacra. Simulations are processes whereby events or situations in the past are replaced with virtual, electronic, or digitized images and signs. While a drama may simulate real life, we generally think of this as representation of some part of the social world – institutions, relationships, and interactions that idealize or characterize aspects of the social world. Television has carried this much further, so that the images simulate many different and hypothetical aspects of social life. Simulacra denote representations of the real but where the essence of the real may be missing. What Baudrillard argues is that these simulacra "are so omnipresent that it is henceforth impossible to distinguish the real from simulacra’ (BK, 1997, p. 101). That is, we live in a society of simulacra so that it no long makes sense to distinguish some underlying reality from the simulacra.
Hyperreality. This is hyperreality – "the blurring of distinctions between the real in the unreal in which the prefix ‘hyper’ signifies more real than real whereby the real is producted according to a model" (BK, 1991, p. 119). This hyperreal is the "end result of a historical simulation process in which the natural world and all its referents have been gradually replaced with technology and self-referential signs" (BK, 1997, p. 101). No longer is there an underlying reality which has an existence apart from the simulations and simulacra. Rather, what we consider to be social reality is indefinitely reproducible and extendable, with the copy indistinguishable from the original, or perhaps seeming more real than the original. Video games become more real than other forms of interaction, theme parks which are simulacra become more desirable than the originals (Las Vegas, Disneyworld), and even nature becomes better viewed through national parks and reconstructions.
Implosion. Baudrillard uses this term to refer to the process whereby the image or simulation and reality collapse on each other and become the same, so that there is no longer any distinction between the two. This is
a process of social entropy leading to a collapse of boundaries, including the implosion of meaning in the media and the implosion of media messages and the social in the masses. … The dissemination of media messages and semiurgy saturates the social field, and meaning and messages flatten each other out in a neutralized flow of information, entertainment, advertising, and politics (Best and Kellner, 1991, p. 121).All the different parts of the social world implode, leaving no separation between formerly distinctive parts of society – politics and sports become entertainment, or the latter become the former. With the O. J. Simpson case, it was difficult to separate entertainment, legal issues, private, public, and the social reality – all imploded together to create a grand spectacle.
If Baudrillard is correct, then earlier forms of social theory may be inadequate to analyse this postmodern society. Earlier analysis focussed on signs, symbols, and meaning (Mead and symbolic interaction), fashion (Simmel), and power of the media (critical theory), but generally argued that these were means by which people communicated based on some underlying social reality. That is, there were subjects or individuals who developed a sense of self through communication, and used this interact with others, thus developing the patterns, institutions, and structures of the social world. Implicit in this form of analysis is that there is a subject and and object (Mead’s other, interaction among individuals in symbolic interaction, etc). Meaning is associated with knowledge and consciousness of others, symbols, and relationships.
Baudrillard argues that the subject-object distinction disappears in the contemporary setting so that signs and symbols do not have meaning in the conventional sense. In fact, meaning itself becomes questionable in these circumstances and he argues that there has been a destruction of meaning in the contemporary era. While there may be meaning associated with earlier forms of social reality, these are "dead meaning and frozen forms mutating into new combinations and permutations of the same" (BK, 1991, p. 127).
While Baudrillard carries through an analysis of hyperreality further than other theorists, and shows some of its implications, he does not appear to have developed an analysis of a way out of this era or even a means of analyzing it sociologically. That is, a sociological analysis provides a means of understanding and critiquing the social world. Baudrillard’s analysis argues that it is not really possible to do this in the conventional manner. Instead, he proposes various strategies and perspectives that people might adopt, but in postmodern fashion does not provide directives or modes of analysis.
d. Fatal Strategies.
Given that the postmodern world lacks meaning and is "where theories float in a void, unanchored in any secure harbour" (BK, 1991, p. 127) how are people to respond? Baudrillard appears to have a number of responses. At one level, he argues that this produces little hope for the future and "melancholy is the quality inherent in the mode of disappearance of meaning, in the mode of volitilisation of meaning in operational systems" (Baudrillard in BK, 1991, p. 127). Despair, sadness, and nostalgia is thus one form of response that people have in the current era, and one response is to attempt to bring back those parts of the past that have been destroyed. This may be associated with a revival or earlier forms of spirituality (new age, fundamentalism, aboriginal), or a recycling of earlier cultural forms (earlier popular music), or outmoded institutional forms (earlier models of family values). At another level, Baudrillard says that the response is a happy one, with playfulness, laughter, hallucinations, ecstacy, seduction, and giddiness, and he talks about orgy and celebration, although he also comments on what is to occur after the orgy (Smart, p. 413).
For Baudrillard, the current era is one where the ideas of progress and production have passed, and where the modern movements of liberation have taken place and the results of these may be reversed. As a result, there is (or at least appears to be) nothing new so there is "indefinite reproduction of ideals, of phantasms, or images, of dreams" (from Smart, p. 413). This failure of modernity to be unable to go further results in a replay of earlier ideas and a recycling of old ideals. While life goes on, the great ideas of progress and production have disappeared.
Baudrillard’s fatal strategies may be considered more inevitable and fatalistic, rather than fatal as deadly, although both are implied by the French (and English) words. His view is that processes have a certain inevitability to them, that things go beyond themselves in an inevitable manner. The result is that they produce a disappearance, end, or finality to the process – not a negation in the dialectic sense, but a loss or erasure of meaning. Baudrillard counterposes this to contradiction, arguing the "the universe is not dialectical: it moves toward the extremes, and not towards equilibrium; it is devoted to a radical antagonisms and not to reconciliation or to synthesis" (Selected Writings, p. 185). The example Smart gives is that of production, where there is more and more production, with faster and faster circulation of production and distribution, but producing an end of the idea of production, that we have passed beyond production. He may have in mind postindustrial society, where production and the ideals of production have been so successful, that a new stage is reached. He argues that this produces a certain banality (triviality, ordinary) here the ideal disappears and becomes so commonplace that it does not have meaning associated with it – "such is the banal destiny of all great ideals in what could be called postmodernity" (Smart, p. 413).
While Baudrillard may not offer a way out, his analysis does provide a certain apt description of contemporary trends that seem quite disparate. Unlike others, such as the critical theorists, Baudrillard does not consider this with regret, but argues that we accept this and adopt strategies in the face of this. Since Baudrillard himself does not have a grand plan to change or create progress, his writings since the early 1980s are more fragmented, ironic, and fantastical. In fact, his writings may be considered to parallel media and society and their unexpected turns, and science fiction of the cyberpunk sort (J. G. Ballard and William Gibson).
One strategy suggested by Baudrillard in Fatal Strategies (1983) is that "individuals should thus surrender to the world of objects, learning their ruses and strategies, and should give up the project of sovereignty and control" (BK, 1991, p. 129). He appears to base this strategy on two considerations. One is that there is nothing new, everything has been done, all philosophic and social theoretical issues have been addressed, and all that is left is to recycle, recombine, and play with these in new ways. A second aspect is that the subject has shown it cannot dominate the object. Progress was associated with the domination of nature and directing the natural and social world in a positive direction. But this has all imploded and become impossible in the current era where subject cannot be distinguished from object, where reality and image cannot be separated, and society takes on a new dynamic.
Baudrillard associates this new society with the victory of the object and "he proposes that we become more like things, like objects, and divest ourselves of the illusion and hubris of subjectivity. Likewise, he proposes that it is useless to change or control the world and that we should give up such subjective strategies and adopt the ‘fatal strategies’ of objects" (BK, 1991, p. 131). This may have some parallels with those who advocate a similar strategy in environmental or ecological issues, but Baudrillard takes this in a different direction. That is, he argues for taking things to their extreme and, by doing, this surpass the limits and subvert the tendencies. Even in consumption he noted that we could consume ever more, even useless and absurd types of consumption. In some sense we have done this, but it has not subverted the consumer society, but likely has entrenched it even more.
The Canadian postmodernist, Arthur Kroker, adopts a more useful fatal strategy. He argues that we can change the new technologies by becoming part of them, getting to know them better, and turning them in a more human direction. But this seems somewhat alien to Baudrillard, since he does not emphasize the humanistic view.
Best and Kellner note that Fatal Strategies is original, but bizarre, and an approach that Baudrillard appears to have abandoned.

e. Readings from Baudrillard
These articles are reprints from the electronic journal C-Theory (www.ctheory.com), edited by Arthur and Marilouise Kroker in Montreal. This is a journal of postmodern theory, with discussion of media related issues.
In these writings, Baudrillard does not carry out a comprehensive or reasoned form of analysis. Rather, these are journalistic articles, attempting to create impressions by giving examples of events and situations that characterize the postmodern world. Baudrillard attempts to be humorous and ironic, with short ideas where he tries to impress readers by example rather than rational argument. The first two articles are translations from the French newspaper Libération, and the third from one of Baudrillard’s books.
i. Disneyworld Company http://www.ctheory.com/e25-disneyworld_comp.html
First page:
Baudrillard considers society to be a spectacle, and argues that things have reached a point where it is difficult to separate the spectacle and social reality – the two are so intertwined through each constructing the other that they are inseparable. Further, to separate these implies that society has some underlying characteristics (human nature, will, solidarity?), and the spectacle is guided by forces such as profits, technological imperatives, or attempts to manipulate the public. The analysis of Baudrillard points to the difficulty of making such assumptions or conclusions, and that the contemporary era is characterized by society itself becoming spectacle or simulation.
In this context, Baudrillard has a fascination with the Disney corporation and its products. These are spectacles, where Disneyland, Disneyworld, and Eurodisney create a virtual reality, but in which "reality becomes a spectacle … where the real becomes a theme park" (3rd ¶). Visitors to Disney quickly realize how they are managed and processed in the name of entertainment and having a good time. The virtual reality of these theme parks becomes a standard for entertainment and a good life, at least in the eyes of some.
Smurfland (1st ¶). Irony of unemployed steel workers becoming the workers of leisure time and when Smurfland failed, they again became unemployed. He might have compared this with Flint, Michigan, where the decline of the auto industry in that city led to mass unemployment and poverty there. The leaders of the city proposed to redevelop the city’s economy by establishing an automobile theme park in the city – i.e. to recover prosperity not by reestablishing the real industry, but by developing the simulation of the industry. Of course, that failed and Flint has only slowly recovered, if at all. Perhaps it has reestablished itself as image though, through the six year old shooting a classmate and by sending its basketball products to Michigan State to capture the NCAA basketball championship.
Disney Pornography (2nd ¶). Fantasy of Disney taking over 42nd street, Times Square region in New York – street with sex shops, porn movies, prostitution, and general sleaziness – and developing this spectacle into a "legitimate" form. In fact, while this is fantastical, this area has been redeveloped as spectacle, although not by Disney.
Gulf War (2nd ¶). Baudrillard has written extensively about the virtual nature of the Gulf War, how it was produced as much for the media and North American audiences and images, as for its actual geopolitical effects. Here Schwarzkopf is reported to have celebrated the end of a virtual war in a theme park that celebrates virtuality.
Real as blood transfusion for the "reality show," the spectacle (3rd ¶). These spectacles feast on the real, but the latter imitate the spectacle, and become the spectacle.
In the 4th ¶, Baudrillard notes that Disney was frozen in liquid nitrogen, presumably hoping to emerge in a different era where things had progressed. In another of his writing, Baudrillard notes that Disney may be surprised if he wakes up in the 15th century, or some other time. In the meantime, people have become extras in the Disney virtual reality.
Also note the reference to the genome project. Baudrillard often uses language or ideas from natural science, often changing their meaning. But here he refers to the resequencing and recombinations of the human gene that are proving possible through genetic engineering. If applied to seeds and human bodies, where does the real end and the virtual begin?
Second page:
1st ¶ refers to the Benetton advertisements that used photographs and images of heroin addicts, AIDS patients, and victims of torture. But his arguments on the influence of fashion on body styles, clothing, and adornments note that "the virtual take over the real as it appears, and then replicates it without any modification."
In the next three paragraphs, Baudrillard argues that reality (the social world) has been cloned and transformed into performance (from Goffman?). That is, the social world has moved beyond the creation of spectacle (the original Disneyland) to a situation where we are "no longer alienated and passive spectators but interactive participants … [in a] huge ‘reality show.’" Unlike Weber or critical theorists, who consider organizations and media to be separated from people, thus creating alienation, in this new world we are not alienated beause we become part of this new reality – although as interactive extras. That is, to be alienated implies a separate and essential form of human nature and well-defined human subject. Baudrillard does not agree that there is such a subject, so that we are neither actors or spectators in the earlier sense. He argues that Disney has won. At one level, he considers this to be obscene, but at another, this is the way things are, and is the postmodern condition and not really reversible.
The last ¶ notes how time has imploded or been collapsed in these circumstances, so that there is no sense of different eras or different times – "all the places and all the periods in a single atemporal virtuality." In addition to theme parks doing this, the juxtaposition of images in the media and the mixing of times, places, and images through the internet confuses time and space and makes it more difficult to remember or imagine real time.
ii. Global Debt and Parallel Universe http://www.ctheory.com/e31-global_debt.html
1st page:
1st ¶ continues the discussion of time – in this case a counting down of time to the millenium – the end of history? The other clock in Times Square reports the mounting debt. Both of these relate to Baudrillard’s fatal strategies – moving to the extreme amounts to a disappearance of the phenomenon.
One example is information – data about the world around us. In an earlier era, by amassing data we may have been able to develop understanding and knowledge of the world around us. But as the amount of information increases until there is information overload, in essence this is a disappearance of information. Note p. 2 of this article where Baudrillard comments on information – "a small dose of information reduces ignorance, a massive dose of artificial intelligence can only reinforce the belief that our natural intelligence is deficient. The worst thing that can happen to an individual is to know too much and, thus, to fall beyond knowledge."
Another example is pornography and sexuality. "Sexuality does not vanish in sublimation, repression and morality. It vanishes more effectively in what is more sexual than sex: pornography. The hypersexual is the contemporary of the hyperreal." (Selected Writings, p. 188). Baudrillard argues that this is a
Dead point: the neutral point where every system crosses the subtle limits of reversibility, contradiction, and reevalutation, in order to be completely absorbed into noncontradiction, in desparate self-contemplation, and in ecstacy … (Selected Writings, p. 190).This is where meaning is erased, since there are not referents and the process no longer has any function or use value.
The disappearance of references (2nd and 3rd ¶) is a new phenomenon according to Baudrillard. The numbers are so large (or small) as to be meaningless, and the speed with which things accelerate and circulate cannot be comprehended or absorbed. The debt acquires its own dynamic, but creates a new social reality. That is, the debt becomes a means of uniting people into a common destiny. Whether this is really a new form is not clear, since political economists have argued for the necessity of debt and noted how the economic system creates a similar fate for all. For example, if the stock market collapses, as in the 1930s, then that creates mass poverty. The situation today could be much worse – so that threat leads to a perpetuation of the debt.
2nd page:
In the 1st ¶ Baudrillard argues that the billboard becomes a spectacle with no real meaning, so that the exaggerated numbers that presumably represent the negative phenomenon of debt, become an advertisement, a triumph of capitalism, an advertising campaign for American dominance. While Baudrillard talks about disappearance and catastrophe, this is only partially real – the jet may crash, but debt continues to grow.
The result is parallel worlds of debt, information, communication – each with their own dynamic. In this sense, Baudrillard comes close to structural analysis, noting that these structures and forces have their own dynamic and effects. At the same time, he tries to avoid the conclusions of this form of analysis by arguing that these are fatal strategies that are separated from our social world (although affecting and uniting it) and best left on their own. In the last two ¶s he argues that creating a more "rational" or inclusive world would not be desirable. For Baudrillard this is a dangerous utopia, although it is not clear what the dangers are. He arguest that it is better to leave these alone, that these are human creations that must be allowed to carry on their own dynamic. In the conclusion he notes that progress once created solidarity, but not it is the threat of catastrophy than does this. Some have interpreted this as resignation on the part of Baudrillard, to make the best of the postmodern condition in which society has placed itself.
Reversion of History http://www.ctheory.com/a-reversion_of_history.html
The first ¶ again notes the disappearance in the limit, as history reaches its end it disintegrates. The result is a reversal and disintegration. In this article, Baudrillard raises a number of questions concerning the recycling of history, the reversibility of modernity and progress, and the emphasis on past problems. On the second page, he notes that we may be able to emphasize the positive features, creating positive memories, in the current period.
ReferencesBaudrillard, Jean. 1988. Selected Writings. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Baudrillard, Jean. 1999. Revenge of the Crystal. London: Pluto Press.
Best, Steven and Douglas Kellner, Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations, New York, The Guilford Press, 1991.
Best, Steven and Douglas Kellner, The Postmodern Turn, New York, The Guilford Press, 1997.
Rosenau, Pauline Marie, Post-Modernism and the Social Sciences: Insights, Inroads and Intrusions, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1992.
Last edited on April 6, 2000.
Return to Sociology 319.


Thursday 8 October 2015

Longinus (literature)

Longinus is the conventional name of the author of the treatise On the Sublime, a work which focuses on the effect of good writing. Longinus, sometimes referred to as Pseudo-Longinus because his real name is unknown, was a Greek teacher of rhetoric or a literary critic who may have lived in the 1st or 3rd century AD. Longinus is known only for On the Sublime. Longinus was greatly influenced by the large amount of traveling he completed in his youth. He journeyed to countless cities such as Athens, Rome and Alexandria. While on these trips, he attended lectures about philosophy, undoubtedly shaping his own beliefs. One of Longinus’ favorite philosophers was Plato.

Authorship of On the Sublime
The author is unknown. In the reference manuscript (Parisinus Graecus 2036), the heading reports “Dionysius or Longinus," an ascription by the medieval copyist that was misread as "by Dionysius Longinus." When the manuscript was being prepared for printed publication, the work was initially attributed to Cassius Longinus (c. 213–273 AD). Since the correct translation includes the possibility of an author named "Dionysius," some have attributed the work to Dionysius of Halicarnassus, a writer of the 1st century AD. There remains the possibility that the work belongs to neither Cassius Longinus nor Dionysius of Halicarnassus, but, rather, some unknown author writing under the Roman Empire, likely in the 1st century. The error does imply that when the codex was written, the trails of the real author were already lost. Neither author can be accepted as the actual writer of the treatise. The former maintained ideas which are absolutely opposite to those written in the treatise; about the latter, there are problems with chronology.

Among further names proposed, are Hermagoras (a rhetorician who lived in Rome during the 1st century AD), Aelius Theon (author of a work which had many ideas in common with those of On the Sublime), and Pompeius Geminus (who was in epistolary conversation with Dionysius).

Dionysius of Halicarnassus
Dionysius of Halicarnassus wrote under Augustus, publishing a number of works. Dionysius is generally dismissed as the potential author of On the Sublime, since the writing officially attributed to Dionysius differs from the work On the Sublime in style and thought.

Cassius Longinus
Accredited with writing a number of literary works, this disciple of Plotinus was "the most distinguished scholar of his day." Cassius received his education at Alexandria and became a teacher himself. First teaching at Athens, Cassius later moved to Asia Minor, where he achieved the position of advisor to the queen of Palmyra, Zenobia. Cassius is also a dubious possibility for author of the treatise, since it is notable that no literature later than the 1st century AD is mentioned (the latest is Cicero, dead in 43 BC), and the work is now usually dated to the early 1st century AD. The work ends with a dissertation on the decay of oratory, a typical subject of the period in which authors such as Tacitus, Petronius and Quintilian, who also dealt with the subject, were still alive. Longinus he was the minister of Queen Zenobia of Palmyra. He was executed by Aurelian, the Roman emperor who conquered Palmyra. The reason for his execution in 273 AD, were on charges of conspiring against the Roman state. This was most likely because of what Longinus had written for Queen Zenobia of Palmyra while she was still in power. Longinus is reported to have written answers for the Queen, which were used in response to Aurelian, the man who would soon rise to power as the Roman emperor.

The treatise On the Sublime
On the Sublime is both a treatise on aesthetics and a work of literary criticism. It is written in an epistolary form and the final part, possibly dealing with public speaking, has been lost.
The treatise is dedicated to Posthumius Terentianus, a cultured Roman and public figure, though little else is known of him. On the Sublime is a compendium of literary exemplars, with about 50 authors spanning 1,000 years mentioned or quoted. Along with the expected examples from Homer and other figures of Greek culture, Longinus refers to a passage from Genesis, which is quite unusual for the 1st century:
A similar effect was achieved by the lawgiver of the Jews—no mean genius, for he both understood and gave expression to the power of the divinity as it deserved—when he wrote at the very beginning of his laws, and I quote his words: "God said,"—what was it?—"Let there be light, and there was. Let there be earth, and there was."
On the Sublime 9.9

Given his positive reference to Genesis, Longinus has been assumed to be either a Hellenized Jew or readily familiar with the Jewish culture. As such, Longinus emphasizes that, to be a truly great writer, authors must have "moral excellence". In fact, critics speculate that Longinus avoided publication in the ancient world "either by modesty or by prudential motives". Moreover, Longinus stresses that transgressive writers are not necessarily shameless fools, even if they take literary risks that seem "bold, lawless, and original". As for social subjectivity, Longinus acknowledges that complete liberty promotes spirit and hope; according to Longinus, "never did a slave become an orator". On the other hand, too much luxury and wealth leads to a decay in eloquence—eloquence being the goal of the sublime writer.

The Sublime
Longinus critically applauds and condemns certain literary works as examples of good or bad styles of writing. Longinus ultimately promotes an "elevation of style" and an essence of "simplicity". To quote this famous author, "the first and most important source of sublimity [is] the power of forming great conceptions." The concept of the sublime is generally accepted to refer to a style of writing that elevates itself "above the ordinary". Finally, Longinus sets out five sources of sublimity: "great thoughts, strong emotions, certain figures of thought and speech, noble diction, and dignified word arrangement".

The effects of the Sublime are: loss of rationality, an alienation leading to identification with the creative process of the artist and a deep emotion mixed in pleasure and exaltation. An example of sublime (which the author quotes in the work) is a poem by Sappho, the so-called Ode to Jealousy, defined as a "Sublime ode". A writer's goal is not so much to express empty feelings, but to arouse emotion in his audience.

In the treatise, the author asserts that "the Sublime leads the listeners not to persuasion, but to ecstasy: for what is wonderful always goes together with a sense of dismay, and prevails over what is only convincing or delightful, since persuasion, as a rule, is within everyone's grasp: whereas, the Sublime, giving to speech an invincible power and [an invincible] strength, rises above every listener".

According to this statement, one could think that the sublime, for Longinus, was only a moment of evasion from reality. But on the contrary, he thought that literature could model a soul, and that a soul could pour itself out into a work of art. In this way the treatise becomes not only a text of literary inquiry, but also one of ethical dissertation, since the Sublime becomes the product of a great soul (μεγαλοφροσύνης πήχημα, megalophrosunēs apēchēma). The sources of the Sublime are of two kinds: inborn sources ("aspiration to vigorous concepts" and "strong and enthusiastic passion") and acquirable sources (rhetorical devices, choice of the right lexicon, and "dignified and high composition").

The ethical aspect and attention to the "great soul" broaden the dimension of the work; begun in order to disprove the arguments of a pamphlet of literary criticism, it ends by creating a new idea within the entire framework of aesthetics. The sublime, in fact, is a denominator of the greatness of the one who approaches to it, both the author's and the viewer's (or reader's). Between them an empathetic bond must arise. Then, the Sublime is a mechanism of recognition (arising from the impact of the work of art) of the greatness of a spirit, of the depth of an idea, of the power of speech. This recognition has its roots in the belief that everyone is aware of the existence of the Sublime, and that the striving towards greatness is rooted in human nature. In the wake of these considerations, the literary genre and the subject-matter chosen by the poet assume a minor importance for Longinus, who affirms that "sublimity" might be found in any or every literary work. He proves to be a very clever critic, for he excels the Apollodoreans by speaking of the critic as a form of positive "channeling" of the Genius. He passes beyond the rigid rules of the literary critics of his time, according to which only a regular (or "second-rate", as Longinus says) style could be defined as perfect.

On the other hand he admires the boldness of the Genius, which always succeeds in reaching the zenith, even if at the expense of forgivable lapses in style. Thus among examples of the Sublime may be rated (not in any order) Homer, the tragedians, Sappho, Plato, even the Bible, and a playwright like Aristophanes (since the author maintained that laughter is a jocose pathos—and therefore, "sublime", being "an emotion of pleasure"). He admires Hellenistic poets like Apollonius of Rhodes and Theocritus for their sophistication, but ranks them below authors of the classical age because they did not take risks and fought shy of the "brave disorder" without which one could not hope to attain the sublime. "Would you prefer to be Homer or Apollonius?... No sane person would give just one tragedy, the Oedipus Rex, in exchange for all Ion's dramas."

The Sublime, moreover, does not manifest itself only in what is simply beautiful, but also in what is sufficiently distressing to cause bewilderment (κπληξις, ekplēxis), wonder θαυμαστόν, to thaumaston) and even fear (φόβος, phobos). It could be said that Helen of Troy may certainly have been the most beautiful woman in the world, but she was never sublime in Greek literature: however Edmund Burke cites the scene of the old men looking at Helen's "terrible" beauty on the ramparts of Troy—he regards it as an instance of the beautiful, but his imagination is captured by its sublimity. Hecuba in Euripides's The Trojan Women is certainly sublime when she expresses her endless sorrow for the terrible destiny of her children.

The decay of rhetoric
The author speaks also about the decay of oratory, as arising not only from absence of personal freedom but also from the corruption of morals, which together destroy that high spirit which generates the Sublime. Thus the treatise is clearly centred in the burning controversy which raged in the 1st century AD in Latin literature. If Petronius pointed out excess of rhetoric and the pompous, unnatural techniques of the schools of eloquence as the causes of decay, Tacitus was nearer to Longinus in thinking that the root of this decadence was the establishment of Princedom, or Empire, which, though it brought stability and peace, also gave rise to censorship and brought an end to freedom of speech. Thus oratory became merely an exercise in style.

Misleading translations and lost data
Translators have been unable to clearly interpret the text, including the title itself. The "sublime" in the title has been translated in various ways, to include senses of elevation and excellent style. The word sublime, argues Rhys Roberts, is misleading, since Longinus' objective broadly concerns "the essentials of a noble and impressive style" than anything more narrow and specific. Moreover, about one-third of the treatise is missing; Longinus' segment on similes, for instance, has only a few words remaining. Matters are further complicated in realizing that ancient writers, Longinus' contemporaries, do not quote or mention the treatise in any way.

Limitations of the writing
Despite Longinus' critical acclaim, his writing is far from perfect. Longinus' occasional enthusiasm becomes "carried away" and creates some confusion as to the meaning of his text. Furthermore, 18th-century critic Edward Burnaby Greene finds Longinus, at times, to be "too refined".  Greene also claims that Longinus' focus on hyperbolical descriptions is "particularly weak, and misapplied." Occasionally, Longinus also falls into a sort of "tediousness" in treating his subjects. The treatise is also limited in its concentration on spiritual transcendence and lack of focus on the way in which language structures determine the feelings and thoughts of writers. Finally, Longinus' treatise is difficult to explain in an academic setting, given the difficulty of the text and lack of "practical rules of a teachable kind."

Writing style and rhetoric
Despite its faults, the treatise remains critically successful because of its "noble tone," "apt precepts," "judicious attitude," and "historical interests". One of the reasons why it is so unlikely that known ancient critics wrote On the Sublime is because the treatise is composed so differently from any other literary work. Since Longinus' rhetorical formula avoids dominating his work, the literature remains "personal and fresh," unique in its originality. Longinus rebels against the popular rhetoric of the time by implicitly attacking ancient theory in its focus on a detailed criticism of words, metaphors, and figures. More explicitly, in refusing to judge tropes as entities unto themselves, Longinus promotes the appreciation of literary devices as they relate to passages as a whole. Essentially, Longinus, rare for a critic of his time, focuses more on "greatness of style" than "technical rules." Despite his criticism of ancient texts, Longinus remains a "master of candor and good-nature". Moreover, the author invents striking images and metaphors, writing almost lyrically at times. In general, Longinus appreciates, and makes use of, simple diction and bold images.

As far as the language is concerned, the work is certainly an "unicum" because it is a blend of expressions of the Hellenistic Koine Greek to which are added elevated constructions, technical expressions, metaphors, classic and rare forms which produce a literary pastiche at the borders of linguistic experimentation.

Influences
In reading On the Sublime, critics have determined that the ancient philosopher and writer Plato is a "great hero" to Longinus. Not only does Longinus come to Plato's defense, but he also attempts to raise his literary standing in opposition to current criticisms. Another influence on the treatise can be found in Longinus' rhetorical figures, which draw from theories by a 1st-century BC writer, Caecilius of Calacte.

Historical criticism and use of On the Sublime
Ø  10th century - The original treatise, before translation, is copied into a medieval manuscript and attributed to "Dionysius or Longinus."
Ø  13th century - A Byzantine rhetorician makes obscure references to what may be Longinus' text.
Ø  16th century - The treatise is ignored by scholars until it is published by Francis Robortello in Basel, in 1554, and Niccolò da Falgano, in 1560. The original work is attributed to "Dionysius Longinus" and most European countries receive translations of the treatise.
Ø  17th century - Sublime effects become a desired end of much Baroque art and literature, and the rediscovered work of "Longinus" goes through half a dozen editions in the 17th century. It is Boileau's 1674 translation of the treatise into French that really starts its career in the history of criticism. Despite its popularity, some critics claim that the treatise was too "primitive" to be truly understood by a "too civilized" 17th-century audience.
Ø  18th century - William Smith's 1739 translation of Longinus on the Sublime established the translator and once more brought the work into prominence. Longinus' text reaches its height in popularity. In England, critics esteem Longinus' principles of composition and balance second only to Aristotle's Poetics. Edmund Burke's A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful and Immanuel Kant's Critique of the Power of Judgment owe a debt to Longinus' concept of the sublime, and the category passes into intellectual discourse. As "Longinus" says, "The effect of elevated language upon an audience is not persuasion but transport," a fitting sentiment for Romantic thinkers and writers who reach beyond logic, to the wellsprings of the Sublime. At the same time, the Romantics gain some contempt for Longinus, given his association with the "rules" of classical poets. Such contempt is ironic, given the widespread influence of Longinus on the shaping of 18th-century criticism.
Ø  19th century - Early in the 19th century, doubts arise to the authorship of the treatise. Thanks to Italian scholar Amati, Cassius Longinus is no longer assumed to be the writer of On the Sublime. Simultaneously, the critical popularity of Longinus' work diminishes greatly; though the work is still in use by scholars, it is rarely quoted. Despite the lack of public enthusiasm, editions and translations of On the Sublime are published at the end of the century.
Ø  20th century - Although the text is still little quoted, it maintains its status, apart from Aristotle's Poetics, as "the most delightful of all the critical works of classical antiquity." Also see Neil Hertz's essay on Longinus in his book, The End of the Line. Hertz is in part responding to Thomas Weiskel's book The Romantic Sublime, probably the most influential recent account of British and German Romantic attitudes towards the Sublime of both Burke and Longinus. Laura Quinney treats the attractions grim demystification in analyzes of Longinus, particularly Weiskel's. Jonathan Culler has an appreciation of Hertz on Longinus in "The Hertzian Sublime." Anne Carson and Louis Marin have occasion to discuss Longinus as well and Harold Bloom and William J. Kennedy have significant accounts of his work. William Carlos Williams also uses three lines from the work as an epigraph to the Prologue to Kora in Hell.

German film director Werner Herzog claims to have an affinity with the work of Longinus, in a talk entitled "On the Absolute, the Sublime and Ecstatic Truth", presented in Milan. Herzog says that he thinks of Longinus as a good friend and considers that Longinus's notions of illumination has a parallel in some moments in his films. He quotes from Longinus: "For our soul is raised out of nature through the truly sublime, sways with high spirits, and is filled with proud joy, as if itself had created what it hears."